There are more strategy-proof procedures than you think
نویسندگان
چکیده
With as few as eight individuals and five alternatives, there are 561, 304, 372, 286, 875, 579, 077, 983 strategy-proof social choice rules. © 2012 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved. The Gibbard–Satterthwaite theorem, now almost 30 years old, has become a staple of microeconomic theory, social choice theory, and mechanism design (Gibbard, 1973; Satterthwaite, 1975). Everyone understands that there are very few strategyproof procedures: Asmany dictatorial rules as there are individuals and a handful of rules that have small range, that select less than all alternatives. But there are more strategy-proof rules than you think. Suppose that there are m alternatives, making up the set X , and n individuals, making up the set N . A coalition is a subset of N . For simplicity, assume that preferences are strong, i.e., antisymmetric as well as transitive. There are then m! possible preference orderings. A profile u is an assignment of one preference ordering, ≻i, to each individual i : u = (≻1, ≻2, . . . ,≻n) and so there are (m!)n profiles. A social choice rule selects one of the alternatives at each profile. There are, therefore, m(m!) n social choice rules. But how many of these rules are strategy-proof? Classified by the size of their range, there are three kinds of strategy-proof rules. (1) Rules with |Range(f )| = 1. There arem such constant rules. (2) Rules with |Range(f )| > 2. Such rules are necessarily dictatorial by the Gibbard–Satterthwaite theorem. So for each such range there are n rules, one for each possible dictator. Of the 2m − 1 non-empty subsets of X , i.e., possible ranges,m are singletons and m 2 = m(m−1) 2 are pairs, so there are 2 m − m − m(m−1) 2 − 1 possible ranges of three or more alternatives. Altogether then, there are n[2m − m − m(m−1) 2 − 1] strategy-proof rules in this category. ∗ Corresponding author. E-mail address: [email protected] (J.S. Kelly). 0165-4896/$ – see front matter© 2012 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved. doi:10.1016/j.mathsocsci.2012.05.001 (3) Rules with |Range(f )| = 2. There are, as noted earlier, m(m−1) 2 possible ranges of two alternatives. Suppose that the range of rule f is {x, y}. If f is strategy-proof, then the value of f at profile u is entirely determined byhow individuals order just x and y at u. If any other part of an individual’s ordering affects the social choice, that individual could manipulate the social choice rule. Accordingly, f is completely characterized by the collection C of winning coalitions for x against y, those coalitions at which f (u) = x when x is preferred to y by exactly the members of that coalition i.e., f (u) = x if and only if {i/x≻i y} ∈ C. The best known example, for an odd number of individuals, is simple majority voting between a pair of alternatives. In this strategy-proof case, C is the collection of all coalitions of cardinality greater than n/2. It is important to observe that this collection satisfies the superset property: J ∈ C and J ⊆ J ⊆ N implies J ∈ C. This generalizes: A rulewith range {x, y} is strategy-proof if and only if the collectionC of coalitionswinning for x against y satisfies the above superset property. Now suppose that we are given a collection of coalitions satisfying the superset property, and define rule f by the condition f (u) = x if and only if {i/x≻i y} ∈ C. Then f is certainly strategy-proof, but does not necessarily have range {x, y}. For example, if C = 2N , then the f determined by C would be a constant rule always selecting x. At the other extreme, if C is empty, so there is no coalition winning for x, the f determined by C would be a constant rule always selecting y. By a chain we mean a collection of coalitions, C, that satisfies the superset property. For all chains except the empty collection or C = 2N , the 264 D.E. Campbell et al. / Mathematical Social Sciences 64 (2012) 263–265 rule defined by f (u) = x if and only if {i/x≻i y} ∈ C, is a strategyproof rule with a range of two. Counting the strategy-proof rules with range of two is equivalent to counting chains. Because a chain satisfies the superset property, it is entirely characterized by its minimal coalitions, where C is a minimal coalition of C if (1) C is an element of C but (2) no proper subset of C is an element of C. The collection M , of minimal coalitions for a strategy-proof rule satisfies the property: If A, B ∈ Mand A ≠ B, then neither A ⊆ B nor B ⊆ A. (∗) (In addition to serving as a determinant of strategy-proof rules, minimal coalitions, according to Riker’s size principle (Riker, 1962), are the winning coalitions we expect to actually observe as they evolve from political competition.) Any collection M of subsets of N satisfying condition (∗) is called an antichain of N . And any collection C of subsets of N satisfying the superset property is called a chain of N . But just as there are chains of N that do not determine a strategy-proof rule of range two, namely the empty collection and 2N so there are two antichains that do not determine strategy-proof rules of range two, namely the empty collection,which yields the constant rule always selecting y, and {∅}, which yields the rule always selecting x. Summarizing, then, the number of strategy-proof rules on two alternatives with a range of both alternatives is M(n) − 2 where M(n) is the number of antichains on N . To illustrate, if n = 3, the list of 20 antichains of {1, 2, 3} is
منابع مشابه
Reading Strategy Use and Field of Study: A Mixed-methods Study
This study was an attempt to explore the reading strategy use of Iranian M.A. students across three different fields of study. Eighty-two M.A. students of power engineering, physics, and communicationwere selected by a Nelson test and the reading comprehension section of a TOEFL. The reading comprehension section of the TOEFL served also as a specific task which helped participants report their...
متن کاملعظمت نمادین حدود و موانع اجرایی آن؛ تأملی فلسفی و جامعهشناختی
Islamic criminal policy has a various kind of punishment that each of them has different logic and purpose. Hadd punishment is based on the criminal behavior and protect the social values for protect moral and social order. So this type of crimes, because of these are the most sever crimes, are punishable with the most severe punishment. Nevertheless, proof of this crime is too hard. Also, ...
متن کاملA New Proof of FDR Control Based on Forward Filtration
For multiple testing problems, Benjamini and Hochberg (1995) proposed the false discovery rate (FDR) as an alternative to the family-wise error rate (FWER). Since then, researchers have provided many proofs to control the FDR under different assumptions. Storey et al. (2004) showed that the rejection threshold of a BH step-up procedure is a stopping time with respect to the reverse filtration g...
متن کاملقانون طلایی تدارک حمایت از دانش آموزان با نیازهای ویژه در کلاسهای فراگیر: از دیگران آنطور حمایت کنید که دوست دارید از شما حمایت کنند
Consider for a moment that the school system paid someone to be with you supporting you 8 hours a day, 5 days a week. Now, imagine that you had no say over who that support person was or how she or he supported you. Or imagine that someone regularly stopped into your place of employment to provide you with one-on-one support. This person was present for all your interactions, escorted you to th...
متن کاملInfantile esotropia: preferred postoperative alignment.
Wagner: This is a case of infantile esotropia. Six weeks following a 6-mm recession of the right and left medial rectus muscles in a 7-month-old infant with typical infantile esotropia findings and no vertical deviation at all, you find a residual esotropia of 12 prism diopters. Dr. Wang, what is your management at this time? Wang: Is the 12 diopters distance, near, or both? Wagner: We’ll say i...
متن کاملذخیره در منابع من
با ذخیره ی این منبع در منابع من، دسترسی به آن را برای استفاده های بعدی آسان تر کنید
عنوان ژورنال:
- Mathematical Social Sciences
دوره 64 شماره
صفحات -
تاریخ انتشار 2012